Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

download Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

of 30

Transcript of Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    1/30

    Beyond Constructivism

    JONATHAN F. OSBORNE

    Kings Colleg e University of London Cornwall

    House

    Waterloo Road London SE1

    8WA U K ; e-rnail: J.Osborne@ kcl.ac.uk

    This article offers a critique of constructivism in science education which is an at-

    tempt to define and identify not only the weaknesses, but the successes of construc-

    tivism. Its success has been to generate a significant body of empirical data which

    has contributed to our knowledge and understanding

    of

    difficulties in the learning of

    science. That knowledge has

    also

    enabled the development of some innovative

    methodology for the pedagogy of science and a greater awareness of the learner.

    However, as a theoretical referent, it suffers from a flawed instrumental epistemol-

    ogy w hich is a misrepresentation of the views and practice of science and scientists.

    Further it has confused the manner in which new knowledge is made with the man-

    ner in which old knowledge is learned, assuming that the two are one and the same

    thing. The result of these failings is that it offers no guidance on adjudication be-

    tween theories, the organization and sequencing of content within the science cur-

    riculum and rejects any value for didacticism. The failure of constructivism to

    recognize its own limitations has lead to it enjoying a hegemony in the research

    comm unity wh ich is undeserved. Instead, it is proposed that an alternative of modest

    realism offers, not only a better representation

    of

    the practice

    of

    science, but addi-

    tionally some value in determining issues of pedagogy.

    1996

    John Wiley Sons,

    Inc.

    INTRODUCTION

    Constructivism in science education has its roots in a reaction against two fea-

    tures dominating science curriculum reforms in the 1960s and 1970s-an episte-

    mology based on naive empiricism (Harris Taylor, 1983) and a developmental

    stage model of cognitive growth which was interpreted as implying deterministic

    limitations to childrens capabilities. Driver and Easley (1978) initiated the reaction

    to these schools of thought when they argued that achievement in science depends

    to a greater extent upon specific abilities and

    prior

    experience than general levels

    of

    cognitive functioning. From here, research based on this premise developed

    rapidly, as did attempts to evolve a theoretical base for the empirical findings, to

    the point where the growth of publications in this field has become almost expo-

    nential (Duit, 1993). Such is the dominance of this school of thought that it has

    been contended that it offers a new paradigm for science education (Tobin et al.,

    Science Education

    80(1): 53-82 (1996)

    1996

    John W iley

    Sons,

    Inc.

    CCC 0036-8326/96/010053-30

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    2/30

    5

    OSBORNE

    1994) and it has acquired implicitly the status of a meta- or grand theory

    (Lyotard, 1984).

    In developing its case, constructivism has focused very strongly on the re-

    silience of the learners beliefs and the social construction of reality. When such

    features are in focus, there are other features which are blurred and out of focus, if

    not out of the picture altogether, and the consequence of the concentration on

    these issues has led to serious epistemological flaws in these constructivists con-

    ceptions of science, that is, the manner in which new knowledge is made.

    Furthermore, to the extent that the personal and social has been given priority

    over the obdurateness of the natural world, it is contended that it fails to distin-

    guish between real and theoretical entities. The result is an instrumentalist episte-

    mology and a misrepresentation of the nature of science through an overemphasis

    of the construction of the concepts, either personally or through discourse, and a

    failure to elaborate any methodology of theory adjudication. Notions of truth have

    simply been replaced by the concept of viability, and the failure to examine how

    one idea could be considered to be more viable than another is at heart a denial

    of objectivity and the rationality of science. Additionally, constructivist pedagogy

    often makes a fallacious connection between the manner in which new scientific

    knowledge is created and the manner in which existing scientific knowledge is

    learned.

    At heart, there is a failure by constructivism to recognize its limits, that is, to

    identify it strengths and its weaknesses. As a method it has had considerable suc-

    cess in its critique of didacticism. Moreover, the types of alternative learning

    strategies it offers, and has generated, have made an important contribution to our

    understanding of the learner and learning (Solomon, 1994). The large body of em-

    pirical data that has been generated by work in this research paradigm has been

    seminal in improving teachers knowledge and understanding of childrens scien-

    tific thinking, its origins and its development. However, as a referent (Tobin

    Tippins, 1993), it suffers from flaws which will always restrict its potential and any

    claims to universality.

    WHY EPISTEMOLOGY MATTERS

    Science earns its place on the curriculum because there is a cultural commitment

    to the value of the knowledge and the practices by which this body of ideas has been

    derived. Hence, any consideration of the theoretical base of science education and its

    practical implementation must start by attempting to resolve the aims and intentions

    of this cultural practice. A variety of useful attempts have been offered. For instance,

    Ogborn (1988) has proposed that science offers the answers to five distinct questions

    which are all important aspects of science education:

    What do we know? (The ontological question.)

    How do we know? (The epistemological question.)

    Why does it happen? (The causal question.)

    What we can do with our knowledge? (The technological question.)

    How we can communicate these ideas? (The communicative questions.)

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    3/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM 55

    From a different perspective, Hodson (1990) distinguishes three dimensions to an ed-

    ucation

    in

    science- learning science, learning to do science, and learning about sci-

    ence. Millar (1995) argues that the aims of science education are to learn something

    about the body of scientific knowledge, something about the processes by which that

    knowledge is generated, and something about the manner in which knowledge is

    so-

    cially constructed. All of these perspectives have one fundamental issue in com-

    mon-that knowledge and understanding of the epistemology of science is an

    essential aspect of any education in science, and any approach which neglects a con-

    sideration of it is incomplete and epistemologically thin. Courses that fail to consider

    how scientists come to know are running the risk of developing students who do not

    acknowledge the scientists views as rational (Duschl, 1990). Some evidence of this

    happening comes from the increasing prevalence of antiscientific beliefs and attitudes

    accompanying the rise in post-material political values in modem youth (Inglehart,

    1990).

    Thus,

    a central thesis of the argument presented here is that epistemology does

    rnatter-because the answer to the question how we know is an important aspect

    of the account of science and the evidence that we present for our ontological com-

    mitments. Science without a serious consideration of this question would leave the

    learner in the position portrayed by Horton in his seminal discussion of the nature of

    African traditional beliefs where he concludes that:

    Th e ground for accepting the m odels proposed by the scientist is often no different

    from the young African villagers ground for accepting the models propounded by

    one of his elders. In both cases the propounders are deferred to as the accredited

    agents of tradition.

    .

    For all the apparent up-to-dateness

    of

    the content

    of

    his

    world-view, the modem Western layman is rarely more open or scientific in his

    outlook than is the traditional African villager.

    Horton, 197

    1 p.

    262

    To transcend that position, an explicit treatment of the procedural basis of Western

    scientific knowledge is essential in science education. This point is also empha-

    sized by Duschl 1990), who contends that to paint a complete picture of science,

    a science curriculum should address not only what is known by science, but also

    how science has come to arrive at such knowledge. Thus, the emphasis on declara-

    tive and propositional knowledge at the expense of the procedural aspect of sci-

    ence, of which the British National Curriculum is a typical example, needs to be

    challenged.

    Furthermore, such a view requires that teachers have some understanding of the

    epistemology of science-that is, the nature of the subject that they present to

    children (Koulaidis Ogborn, 1995; Shulman, 1986). While any treatment of the

    nature of science is problematic, as the writings of Popper, Kuhn, Feyerabend, and

    Lakatos show that there is no agreement that there is one methodological base to

    science (Laudan et al., 1986), this does not mean it is correct to assume that it is

    an irrational practice that has

    no

    methods. Science has a range and variety of

    methods and it is important that science education generates some understanding

    of how the practices of science legitimizes its knowledge claims. For, if one of the

    aspirations of science education is to develop critical thinkers able to understand

    and examine the myriad claims made on a scientific or pseudo-scientific basis,

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    4/30

    56 OSBORNE

    children will need to acquire a good set of intellectual tools. One of these is an un-

    derstanding of how the processes deployed by scientists to ensure their reliability

    and validity of their knowledge. Thus, concepts of fair testing, the identification

    and control of variables, the generation of sound hypotheses, the recognition and

    measurement of sources of error, the criteria by which one theory is distinguished

    from another, repetition of experimental determination, and the use of averaging

    are all essential ideas that enable scientific knowledge to be distinguished from

    pseudo-science.

    A

    science education that omits discussion of these aspects or pre-

    sents a flawed epistemology, is the intellectual equivalent of giving a child a ham-

    mer without the nails.

    The view that an understanding of the epistemology of science is an important

    component of science education is based firmly in the belief that:

    Science effects styles of thinking and reasoning in society;

    it

    influences the accept-

    able modes of rational and reasonable debate; it contributes to public intelligence by

    insti lling a concern for evidence and its rational and open appraisal. For all its faults,

    the scientific tradition has promoted rationality, critical thinking and objectivity. It

    instil ls a concern for evidence , and for having ideas judged not by personal or social

    interest, but by how the world is. Matthews,

    1995,

    p. 2)

    Put simply, the justification of the place and time for science education on the cur-

    riculum lies in the claim that the methods of science and scientists produce reliable

    knowledge, that is, that its epistemology is superior to that of astrologers and even

    sociologists. Thus, any account of science requires a clear and well-defined under-

    standing of the nature of the knowledge claims that science makes.

    CONSTRUCTIVIST EPISTEMOLOGY

    What then can be said of constructivist epistemology? The two most clearly

    elaborated epistemological positions of constructivism are those of the radical con-

    structivist and the social constructivist, both of which will be examined. Their

    ideas need to be contrasted with those of traditional epistemology, which is based

    on the view that knowledge is a success term. Successful in the sense that A is able

    to make a claim

    p

    about the world because (a) p is a true statement about the

    world; (b) A believes

    p;

    and (c) A has a tethering reason for believing in p. In this

    manner, knowledge is

    to

    be distinguished from opinion and the requirement for

    reason as the path from evidence to knowledge is the foundation of the rationality

    of science.

    Radical constructivism is a deliberate and public attempt to move away from such

    an epistemological base. For instance, Glaserfeld (1993)argues that radical construc-

    tivism is postepistemological and an attempt to cut loose from the philosophical tra-

    dition that knowledge has to be a representation of reality. Instead, truth is replaced

    by the notion of viability. Rightly, Glaserfeld recognizes that this is a stark step.

    Essentially for him, knowledge is always the result of a constructive activity, and

    therefore cannot be transferred to a passive receiver. Thus knowledge exists only in

    the mind of cognizing beings, where it is construed, and is not to be found, for in-

    stance, in books, texts, or other traditional repositories of human knowledge which

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    5/30

    BEYOND

    CONSTRUCTIVISM

    57

    simply represent symbols open to a range of interpretation. Hence there is no knowl-

    edge without a knower.

    This is not to say that radical constructivist are solipsists. For, as Tobin argues:

    Constructivism is a set of beliefs about knowledge that begins with the assumption

    that reality exists but cannot be known as a set of truths. Tobin et al., 1994,p. 47)

    At the heart of many radical constructivist writings seems to be a desire to escape no-

    tions of absolute truth, which are accurate or even partial representations of the real

    world. For instance, Tobin suggests that:

    We construct a model of gravity that is viable in that the model fits experience, but

    no matter how elegant, that model cannot claim to

    be an

    absolute truth. Tobin

    Tippins,

    1993,

    p.

    2)

    Furthermore, he continues that we cannot tell whether our model for gravity gets

    closer to an absolute reality. Instead these authors epistemology requires only that

    knowledge is viable because of its coherence with other understandings and it fits

    with experience. Thus truth becomes an act of faith, and knowledge has pragmatic

    validity in that truth is what works. The only requirements should be that it fits with

    experience and is coherent and subject to empirical verification both personally and

    in the wider society.

    There are a number of epistemological problems with this position. First, it at-

    taches itself to the bivalence principle, knowledge is either true or false, and since

    we can never know absolute truth, all knowledge is only subjective, provisional

    and uncertain. For the radical constructivist, there is no halfway house, no asymp-

    totic approach to any zenith of human understanding and no admission that what

    we know improves and increases. Thus the unattainable best is used to drive out

    the attainable better (Ogborn, 1994), and instead, we are simply abandoned on the

    ocean of experience condemned to search for knowledge that is viable. Better

    ideas may be developed in the sense that they are more viable, and fit with expe-

    rience, but we are not necessarily nearer an objective representation of the physical

    world.

    The position of the radical constructivist is essentially that of the instrumentalist.

    Like the latter, theories are merely portrayed as convenient devices for describing

    phenomena and connecting one set of events with another. They are best understood

    as useful fictions which bear no necessary relationship with reality and one idea is

    only considered better than another only if it is a more useful calculating and predic-

    tive device. Such a position is most aptly summarized by Osianders comment in the

    17th century on the theories of Copernicus:

    For

    these hypotheses need not be true or even probable; if they provide a calculus

    consistent with the observations that alone is sufficient. Rosen, 1962,p. 125)

    However, the problem for the instrumentalist is that these theoretical fictions have an

    unfortunate habit of predicting objects, which due to the advances in technology and

    instrumentation can increasingly be seen or sensed. Thus, KekulCs benzene ring

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    6/30

    58 OSBORNE

    structures are revealed by the electron microscope, Maxwells dynamical field struc-

    tures are made tangible by Hertz, Einsteins predictions of the stimulated emission of

    radiation lead to the development of a technological artifact which is a daily, com-

    monplace occurrence.

    The constructivist position is essentially similar to that of philosophers like Rorty

    1989),

    an influential postmodernist, who argues that reality is indifferent to our de-

    scriptions of it and sees language not merely as a tool for expression and representa-

    tion but the means by which the human self is created. For Rorty, arguments about

    truth and realism are irrelevant as there is no metaphysical position which transcends

    the limitation of our own vocabulary and would allow us to adjudicate between com-

    peting knowledge claims. Therefore, the interesting question becomes not How do

    you know? but Why do you talk that way? Rorty is correct in stating that reality is

    indifferent to our description of it and there are often multiple interpretations for the

    same event

    or

    observation, but in science, our language is

    bound by

    reality. For sci-

    ence does have a well established methodology and acts of reference for deciding be-

    tween competing theoretical descriptions and rejecting those which are clearly

    fallible, incomplete, or simply false. Furthermore, the content of the scientific knowl-

    edge that forms the substance of science education is not some transient, uncertain

    representation, where one theory is replaced by another that is incommensurable, for:

    If scien ce is all that ephem eral, if Newtons second law must be classed as a tempo-

    rary codex, it is somewhat surprising that science has been as useful as it has in hu-

    man understanding. Weinberg, 1968, p. 74)

    But how is the child to judge that the scientists description is more viable? How is

    the child to know that there are entities for which we have well-established argu-

    ments for their existence and reliable theories that have superior explanatory power

    than those of common-sense reasoning? Constructivism singularly fails to elaborate

    any mechanism by which one theory can be considered more viable than another.

    Glaserfeld (1991) asks merely that we try to develop a theory which offers a rela-

    tively coherent explanation and that such theories are tested in the experiential

    world where they either do or do not do what they are claimed to do. The problem

    is that many theories, including Ptolemaic astronomy, would meet such criteria.

    Tobin, at least, implicitly (see previous quotation) recognizes that some theories are

    more elegant than others but fails to elaborate any criteria by which such judg-

    ments could, or should, be made. In defending the notion of viability, he argues:

    .

    that knowledge must be viable not on ly personally, but also in the social con-

    texts in which actions do occur. Viability is therefore determined with respect to

    those actions which facilitate the attainment

    of

    goals in the social contexts

    of

    action.

    Tobin Tippins,

    1993,

    p.

    3)

    However, all this argument does is extend the notion that ideas must be personally

    viable to the idea that they must be viable within a social context. Yet again, it fails to

    elaborate any criteria that determine the concept of viability.

    A

    full consideration of how we adjudicate between theories would require an ac-

    knowledgment that our language and our ideas are constrained by reality, to real re-

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    7/30

    BEYOND

    CONSTRUCTIVISM

    59

    ferents that do exist, and thus, while there may be no ultimate check that any con-

    struction is right, there are checks that one construction is better than another. The

    failure to recognize this important practice of science leads implicitly toward a rela-

    tivist ontology where viability is equated with validity so that any viable theory is

    considered worthy of consideration.

    Consequently, a fundamental epistemic problem for constructivism is a failure to

    consider the issue of theory adjudication and articulate a mechanism to establish how

    one theory may be considered to be better than another. Science becomes a set of

    meanings and concepts which evolve from socially negotiated understandings and

    not from a process of examining whether such inventions are supported when tested

    against the real world. Thus, the childs common conception that the sun moves

    round the earth clearly satisfies the radical constructivists epistemological criteria

    that it is both viable and fits with experience. Moreover, such understanding may be a

    socially negotiated product of the classroom or playground but on what basis is it to

    be found wanting? For the scientist, theories are successful because they offer a

    range of explanation, non- ad hocness, consistency with empirical evidence, and log-

    ical consistency which gives them explanatory force that inductive generalizations

    lack (Samarapungvan,

    1992).

    Theories that offer parsimony and that accrue the epis-

    temological status acquired by earlier theories are also preferred. The point here is

    not to elaborate all the criteria by which theories are judged but simply to show that

    such explicit criteria

    do exist

    and are deployed by scientists in making judgments

    about their knowledge claims.

    Such authors seem unaware of the interest and debate in the philosophy of science

    which has given much prominence to the criteria for theory selection and the impor-

    tance of this issue to the epistemology of science (Giere,

    1984;

    Laudan et al.,

    1986).

    In part, the failure to explicate the methods and criteria of science may be because of

    the attack from the sociologists of science who argue that:

    the conviction that a body of practices widely regarded by outsiders as well or-

    ganised , logical and coherent, in fact consists of a disordered array of observations

    with which scientist struggle to produce order. Latour Woolgar, 1986, p. 36)

    Thus, scientific activity is not about nature, but is a fierce fight to construct reality,

    and consequently:

    science is a form of fiction

    or

    discourse like any other, one effect of which is

    the truth effect, which like all literary effects ) arises from textual characteristics,

    such as the tense o f verbs, the structure of enunciation, modalities and

    so

    on. Latour

    Woolgar, 1986, p. 184

    Clearly, the view projected here is that science is a cultural product, distinguishable

    only by its form and not its methods. These interpretations of science (Collins,

    1985;

    Latour,

    1985;

    Pickering,

    1984)

    would deny that scientists deploy a set of criteria in a

    rational and consistent manner to evaluate their ideas. In essence, their argument is

    that the claims of science to follow explicit prespecified procedural rules, to possess

    explicit criteria for correctly recognizing cases, to have complete justifications at

    each step, and to have clear predetermined goals are simply not tenable. Anything

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    8/30

    6

    OSBORNE

    more than a superficial examination of scientific practices shows that all of these fea-

    tures are never present, thus the knowledge claims associated with science lack the

    rationality and the truth they seek to assert. Science thus creates the illusion of cer-

    tainty.

    However, a closer examination of their argument shows that it lacks credibility.

    Scientists clearly do

    h ve

    criteria for judging specific evidence for and against any

    given theoretical position. The fact that all criteria are not always applied or used in a

    consistent manner is not a justification for questioning the whole edifice of science.

    Such an action is rather like a composer discarding a whole symphony because of a

    few bad notes. Scientific thinking is a social construct and scientists do work in com-

    munities of practice with established norms. Radical ideas are never easily accepted

    and occasionally can result in a collapse of the moral order that constitutes the prac-

    tice of science. But the lack of consistency in the application of rules to its epistemic

    practices does not mean that the scientists epistemology lacks any rules. There are

    clear rational arguments why general relativity is a better description of nature than

    Newtons cosmos or why Mendelian genetics is to be preferred as an explanation of

    inherited characteristics compared to Lamarkian theory. Unfortunately, constructivist

    epistemology fails to acknowledge these claims and, in

    so

    doing, undermines the

    very core of what makes scientific knowledge different from other forms of knowl-

    edge. For, if the epistemology it argues for is a fallacious representation of science, a

    form of discourse like any other, why should the knowledge and products of scien-

    tific discourse be given any authority? Science leaves itself with no defense against

    the argument that it is a self-sustained delusion vehemently mounted by the historian

    Bernard in Stoppards play Arcadia:

    A great philosopher is an urgent need. Theres no rush for Isaac N ewton. We were

    quite happy with Aristotles cosmos. Personally, I preferred it. Fifty-five crystal

    spheres geared to Gods crankshaft is my idea of satisfying universe.

    I

    cant think o f

    anything more trivial than the speed

    of

    light. Quarks, quasars-big bangs, black

    holes-who give s a damn? How did you people con

    us

    out of all that status? All that

    money? And why are you

    so

    pleased with yourselves? Stoppard, 1993)

    SOCIAL CONSTRUCTIVISM

    The social constructivist perspective portrays science education as a process of en-

    culturation in which the aspirant members of a culture learn from their tutors and

    that novices are introduced to a community of knowledge through discourse in the

    context of relevant task (Driver et al.,

    1994).

    What might be termed the strong form

    of this position argues that learning is a form of cultural apprenticeship and that cog-

    nition is situated in specific contexts (Lave, 1988; Brown et al. 1989); that is, that

    learning cannot be separated from the context of learning. Now in that learning to be

    a scientist, or to understand what a scientist does, is a process of cognitive appren-

    ticeship there is no quarrel. If as Harrk (1986) argues, science represents the epit-

    omy of rational cooperation set within a strict moral order this is best appreciated

    from working within the discipline or a context that replicates it as near as possible.

    That schools often fail to do this is accepted and the consequence is, as Brown et al.

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    9/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM 61

    (1989) argue, that science education has become a set of ersatz activities which are

    not those of scientists. What is missing from their account is any understanding of the

    rules and practices that guide the scientific community. They present an opaque epis-

    temology where knowledge indexes the situation in which it arises and is used

    which becomes coded by and connected to the activity and environment in which it is

    developed. Epistemological considerations of how it is coded or connected to the

    activity are never discussed.

    Driver et al. (1994a) do at least define what they see as the core ontological com-

    mitments associated with the practice of science. For them:

    scientific knowledge is sym bolic in nature and socially negotiated. Th e objects

    of science are not the phenomena of nature but constructs that are advanced by the

    scientific community to interpret nature. Driver et al., 1994a, p. 5

    Thus, the things of science are no longer entities that populate a real world but the

    inventions of a scientific discourse which are imposed on the phenomena. Hence it

    is not nature which limits the scientific imagination but simply human capabilities

    and their cultural and conceptual tools which reflect the cumulative wisdom of the

    culture. Basically the confusion that occurs here is to conflate ideas and objects, that

    is, to fail to discriminate between the objects of the discourse with the statements of

    the discourse. The two are not the same, one exists and can be experienced, often

    with the aid of instrumentation, the other is a socially negotiated construct.

    The result is that the social constructivist would portray the world as being full of

    peculiar symbolic entities such as atoms, electrons, ions, fields, genes, and chromo-

    somes. These are organized by such ideas as evolution or the nuclear model of the

    atom, but essentially there is nothing special about the truth of science. Science is

    compared to learning a foreign language so that

    If some foreign languages are more difficult for you to learn than others, that is

    mainly because they are less like the language you already know,

    or

    the experiences

    they represent are less familiar. Science has its own distinctive genres, its thematic

    formations, its practical skills. In their forms they are no mo re intellectually complex

    or difficult than those of any other subject. They

    are

    less familiar, less like what we

    already used to. Lemke, 1990, p. 139)

    Lemke extends this position further to argue that every statement of fact is a state-

    ment that is useful for some purposes to act as if something were true. Theories and

    hypotheses are just that, statements useful for some purposes. Once again, this is

    the instrumentalist vision of science, and again the mistake made here is not the rep-

    resentation of science as a human product which is socially constructed, but to con-

    fuse the manner in which knowledge is made with the objects of knowledge

    themselves. They are not one and the same thing. Lemkes argument would appear to

    be that learning science is no different from the problems faced in learning English or

    history, and is distinguishable only by the form and content of the discourse and not

    by the manner in which that knowledge is produced. Thus, learning science is simply

    a matter of learning to talk the right language. Furthermore, the hallmark that distin-

    guishes these two forms of knowledge is not what they describe, but how they

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    10/30

    62 OSBORNE

    describe the world. Essentially for the social constructivist, scientific theory does not

    describe the world, but on the contrary, constitutes it.

    Close examination of some of the sample scripts offered by Driver et al. (1994a) as

    exemplars of the construction

    of

    scientific knowledge shows the nature of this prob-

    lem. The authors use these to argue that they illustrate the discursive nature of scien-

    tific knowledge from which children have to make personal sense. The teacher is

    presented as a guide mediating and negotiating between the childrens everyday

    world and that of science. Yet never once within the several dialogues does the

    teacher address important epistemological issues and ask of the student How do you

    know?; How would you justify that view?;

    or

    Why do you believe you are

    right? That is, the issue of evidence and the act of reference are omitted, and in-

    stead, the function of the teacher is to negotiate with, and persuade the student

    toward a scientific way of seeing through discourse. Yet

    in

    what way is such practice

    to be distinguished epistemically from Hortons African child who is imbued with his

    forms of thought through the oral culture of his tribe?

    For the realist, even the modest realist, such a position is unacceptable.

    Scientists act on the world, they intervene, manipulate, and measure. Their lan-

    guage and discourse acts are limited, not by their imaginations or cultural condi-

    tioning, but by the evidence they gather from such actions on the world. For we

    may think what we like, but we cannot do what we like. Thus, nature always cons-

    trains our discourse:

    The world contains natural substances with peculiar properties. These

    obey

    laws

    which fix the infinite) range

    of

    possible ways in which the natural substances be-

    have in given circumstances. Some of the possible ways in which these substances

    behave are revealed in the quite contingent course of the actual history

    of

    the world

    without any.human intervention. Other possible ways are revealed when humans in-

    tervene contingently in natural processes, for examp le, in the laboratory. Th e human

    intervention

    is

    such that, with the growth of theory constructed by hum ans), we are

    able to manu facture, in the laboratory, new m aterials that would not have emerged in

    the history of the world without hum an intervention. We might say that natures sub-

    stances have underlying dispositions, or powers, some of which will be exhibited

    while others may not be triggered at all. This is a quite traditional metaphysi-

    cal picture which I think accommodates much of what constructivists wish to say

    about science without indulging in radical worldmaking. Nola, 1995 a)

    The social constructivist stands in sharp contrast to this position. For instance

    Latours third rule of method (Latour, 1985) argues that since the settlement of a

    controversy is the cause of Natures representation, not the consequence, we can

    never use the outcome-Nature-to explain how and why a controversy has been

    settled (Latour, 1985). Thus, science is portrayed as a way of world-making rather

    than being made by the world.

    Ultimately, the social constructivist who sees knowledge as primarily fashioned

    and made by human discourse has no defense to the contention that science is an irra-

    tional enterprise where persuasion and force of argument are the main criteria by

    which theories are to be judged. The realists defense of such accusations lies in the

    fact that their discourse acts refer and their veracity can be checked by careful repli-

    cation of the knowledge claims.

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    11/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM

    63

    CONSTRUCTIVIST PEDAGOGY

    How is constructivist theory applied to the process of teaching and learning?

    Tobin and Tippins (1993) make a useful distinction when they ask whether con-

    structivism is a method or a referent.

    A s

    a method, its value is for the production of

    effective pedagogic practices; as a referent, it offers a general and wide-ranging

    theory of learning. Tobin and Tippins see the former as a devaluation of the power

    of constructivism. However, it is perhaps as a method that constructivism has had

    the most value in education. The strong message of this body of research has been

    to expose the difficulty large numbers of children experience in internalizing the

    explanatory models of science and applying them correctly. Such data has in-

    evitably raised the dilemma of how to respond to this research evidence. The con-

    structivist response has been twofold. First, there has been an attack on the notion

    that children are atheoretical (Carey, 1985) and the notion that teaching is a process

    of filling empty minds or tabula rasa (Driver, 1989; Driver Oldham, 1985;

    Gilbert et al., 1982; Hewson, 1981). Solomon (1994) has identified the greatest

    success of constructivism when she argues that redescribing a network of related

    things by a new vocabulary creates a pattern of language which itself constituted a

    new theory. The shift in describing pupil errors from mistakes, of no theoretical

    interest, to misconceptions, or more often alternative frameworks, changed the

    commonplace and unremarkable to something significant. Much of the initial ap-

    peal of this research lies in the way its findings give significance to the everyday

    experience of the teacher. Therefore, constructivism has encouraged teachers and

    curriculum developers to alter their perceptions of children from individuals who

    are irrational and unknowing to cognizant beings who have well-developed theo-

    ries. Formal elicitation of this knowledge as proposed by Driver and Oldham

    (1985) now becomes important for two purposes-to encourage the child to clarify

    and articulate their own understanding; and as a process of formative assessment

    by the teacher to ascertain the teaching and learning needs of their students.

    Teaching becomes a process where understanding and knowledge are no longer

    transmitted but negotiated (Sainsbury, 1992) through a process of cognitive appren-

    ticeship (Brown et al., 1989).

    Constructivists then rightly turned their attention to the learner arguing cor-

    rectly that he or she is responsible for their own learning (Osborne Wittrock,

    1985; Novak Gowin, 1984; Pope, 1985; White, 1988). Here, after all, in the

    learners mind, was where new meanings had to be formulated and understood.

    This could only be achieved if he or she was an active participant in the learning

    process. Hence, their pedagogy has concerned itself with a program of activities

    from which knowledge can be generated or acquired. These tasks focus on the in-

    dividual subject asking them to articulate and use their reasoning in a set of struc-

    tured exercises often making use of groups. Many of the earlier schemes made

    good use of group discussion and poster-making for such purposes (Nussbaum

    Novak, 1981; Cosgrove et al., 1984;

    CLIS

    Project, 1987) and such processes en-

    able the social construction of meaning which is an essential aspect of science ed-

    ucation. Further work by many researchers in the field has led to the production of

    a wide range of structured techniques that require the active participation of the

    student, and one recent book (Baird Northfield, 1992) gives details of more

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    12/30

    64 OSBORNE

    than 80 such techniques. Notable among these structured strategies are predict-

    observe-explain sequences (White, 1988; White Gunstone, 1992); discussion

    of instances of physical phenomena (White Gunstone, 1992); concept mapping

    (Novak Gowin, 1984); word association (Shavelson, 1974); and active reading

    techniques commonly called DARTS (directed activities related to text) (Davies

    Greene, 1984). However, it should be noted that neither of the latter two strategies

    were the product of an explicitly constructivist approach to pedagogy, and cur-

    rently, there is only limited research evidence for the value of any of these ap-

    proaches. One notable exception is Hortons (1992) recent meta-analysis of 18

    studies of concept mapping that met strict criteria of well-defined experimental

    models with controls for which he found 16 that produced positive learning gains

    for the experimental groups. For the sake of establishing their case, more empiri-

    cal studies of this nature are essential to justify the value of constructivist ap-

    proaches to teaching and learning.

    Moreover, the other great contribution of empirical research conducted from this

    paradigm has been the provision of a very broad and detailed knowledge of chil-

    drens thinking and the problems that they encounter with scientific ideas.

    Making

    Sense

    of

    Secondary Science

    by Driver et al. (1994b), is an excellent summary of

    work that has provided useful insights into the common-sense origins of childrens

    thinking and the stages of its development within a domain which have guided both

    curriculum developers and teachers.

    For Tobin, however, the appeal of constructivism is not as a method, nor in the em-

    pirical research findings, but its wider potential as a referent:

    To be a viable theory of knowing, constructivism m ust have explanatory power in all

    situations in which knowledge is constructed.

    .

    Thus constructivism can be used

    as a referent to analyse the learning potential of any situation. Tobin et al., 1994,

    P

    47)

    Such claims are tinged with the view that constructivism is a grand theory, applic-

    able to all instances and not simply a view of learning that has partial value.

    However, as a referent, the limitations of constructivism are indicated by a num-

    ber of omissions. First, there is the failure to use the theory, as opposed to the em-

    pirical research findings, to predict or discuss what it might imply for the content

    and process of science education, and to derive any detailed propositions which

    could in principle be empirically tested. For instance, the term metacognition is

    used to describe the thinking generated by active learning. Yet the lack of any the-

    oretical treatment that adequately describes such activity inevitably leads to more

    unanswered questions. Are all pupils capable of metacognitive activity or just

    some?

    Is

    there a critical age below which children cannot be metacognitive?

    Is

    all

    such activity beneficial? Most published work on the topic (White Mitchell,

    1994; Gunstone, 1991) very much takes the pragmatic view that metacognition is

    inherently a good thing and fails to make Browns (1987) important distinction

    between knowledge of cognition and the regulation of cognition, or to note

    her point that most workers in the field have found little evidence of the former

    before adolescence. So, while the interest in metacognition and the notion that the

    pupil should be active is laudable, such omissions make it questionable whether

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    13/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM

    65

    constructivist theory is sufficiently comprehensive to be adopted as a universal

    referent.

    Second, the question of content inevitably re-emerges. The question that needs

    to be asked is: Metacognitive about what? To the teacher and the curriculum de-

    veloper such decisions are the bread and butter of their daily lives as they attempt

    to order content to form a coherent introduction to science, and to select material

    which stimulates but is not overdemanding. As a referent, constructivist accounts

    of science education have nothing to say other than the familiar Ausubelian re-

    frain. The problem of the determination of content is compounded by the fact that

    the theoretical base in Ausubelian psychology and that of Kelly 1955) has never

    been developed into a model which would enable predictions to be made of what

    material will or will not be accessible to learners. The much quoted statement of

    Ausubel

    1968)

    on the significance of educational psychology is essentially noth-

    ing more than a statement of good common sense, and the success of construc-

    tivism has come from reminding teachers that children do have ideas and theories

    and that their thinking is the foundation on which new meanings must be formu-

    lated.

    A more serious criticism of the constructivist theory is that it provides no well-

    defined mechanism by which the individual can develop new constructs with which

    to see the world. From whence come the ideas with which the individual is to inter-

    pret their sensory perceptions? Where, for instance, is the role of analogy and

    metaphor which are the vehicles for extending our thinking and ideas and reorganiz-

    ing our internal symbolic representations? For example, to observe Brownian motion

    in a smoke cell, a student has to be provided by a teacher with a construct that will

    enable them to make sense of their perceptions prior to observation. This can only be

    done through the use of a taught analogy or comparison. Without this, the common

    experience is that the students attention is needlessly focused on other elements in

    the microscope. Moreover, reformulation of sensation will only occur by reflection

    and reorganization of the representations, something which Cosgrove et al. acknowl-

    edge when they state:

    We are increasingly aware that conceptual change takes tim e and that it is important

    that counterintuitive ideas are considered at regular intervals over a period

    of

    time.

    Cosgrove et al., 1984,p. 254)

    What is omitted from the constructivist writings in science education is comprehen-

    sive account of those processes which would help the individual to generate new

    ideas and concepts, for reinterpreting experience, and transcending common-sense

    reasoning. Intervention studies have predominantly focused on conceptual conflict

    (Cosgrove et al., 1984; Gunstone White, 1981; Hewson Hewson, 1984; Stavy

    Berkovitz,

    1980;

    Thorley Treagust,

    1986)

    which have shown has only limited ef-

    fectiveness (Cosgrove et al., 1984; Rowel1 Dawson, 1983). In addition, school

    practical apparatus is notoriously unreliable as a method of providing direct experi-

    ence of phenomena and is not a good vehicle for developing theory (Osborne, 1990;

    Woolnough Allsop,

    1986).

    Driver herself does in fact come near to confronting

    this very issue when she states:

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    14/30

    66 OSBORNE

    The theoreticalmodels and scientific

    conventions

    will not be

    discovered

    by chil-

    dren through their practical work. They need to

    be

    presented.

    Guidance is

    then

    needed to help children assimilate their practical experiences into what is possibly

    a

    new way

    of

    thinking about them. (Driver, 1983,p. 9)

    But, in her later seminal study on a constructivist view toward curriculum develop-

    ment (Driver Oldham, 1985), this matter is avoided as we are told that we can

    specify the experiences which students should be exposed to but are given no prin-

    ciples on which to make such judgments other than knowing where students are

    starting from and a reliance on the teachers intuitive knowledge of classroom reali-

    ties. The curriculum process itself contains an evaluation phase where pupils test a

    range of ideas including the scientific one if they have suggested it. But what if

    they have not? (On this issue the authors remain silent.) In a more recent position pa-

    per from the Leeds constructivists (Driver et al., 1994a), only once in all the exem-

    plars used to illustrate their conception of the process of learning does the teacher

    assert some scientific knowledge and, even then, without justification. Therefore,

    constructivists, and science educators in general, must recognize that there is a role

    for telling, showing, and seeing as methods which enable the construction of new

    knowledge.

    Faced with the theoretical problem of the determining content, one can only con-

    clude that constructivism has eschewed the issue. Instead, workers in the field have

    resorted to an individualistic approach, arguing that opportunities must be provided

    for the learner to externalize their understanding and this must then be challenged

    by

    critical incidents which generate conceptual conflict (Driver Oldham, 1985), in

    such a manner that the new ideas are plausible, intelligible and fruitful (Hewson

    Hewson, 1984). -While such strategies are a valuable contribution to the teachers

    repertoire, they are not a complete account of the teaching process.

    For instance, as a comprehensive referent, any perspective requires a considera-

    tion of whether the student has the cognitive tools to undertake the manipulation of

    symbols and whether there is age-related development in such facilities. For some

    science educators (Adey Shayer, 1994; Shayer Adey,

    1981),

    sequencing of

    content is possibly the most important issue. However, the instrumental epistemol-

    ogy of the radical or social constructivist fails to recognize any distinctions in the

    complexity and difficulty of theoretical descriptions of real objects, or that some of

    the idealizations of science describe concepts which are

    not

    accessible to sensa-

    tion or experience, for example, energy, but have to be formulated through a

    process of reflective abstraction. While the notion that knowledge is personally

    constructed is at one level a trivial truism, the operational processes required for

    the construction of knowledge are complex, poorly understood, and nontrivial. The

    whole issue of conceptual complexity and whether there are developmental limita-

    tions on childrens capacity to undertake such reasoning is an issue that a construc-

    tivist theory ignores.

    Finally, constructivist theory suffers from another confusion that questions its va-

    lidity as a referent. The metaphor consistently underpinning constructivism is that of

    knowledge as made, produced, generated by the individual (e.g., making sense).

    For instance, Glaserfeld (1987) argues that

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    15/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM 67

    The cognitive organism tries to make sense of experience in order to better avoid

    clashing with the worlds constrain ts. Basica lly to have learned means to

    have drawn conclusions from experience and act accordingly. Glaserfeld, 1987,

    p. 8)

    Yet the emphasis on experience as the manner in which the individual learns is

    strongly associated with a second metaphor of knowledge as found, lying around

    out there to be discovered by the curious. The first metaphor is what the individual

    has to do to learn and acquire new knowledge. Any individual when confronted

    with a new phenomenon has to construct and internalize a meaningful representa-

    tion for themselves-in such a manner is knowledge made by the individual.

    The latter metaphor, which is ironically that of inductivism, is one perception of

    how new scientific knowledge is produced but is rarely the manner in which old

    knowledge is learned in the classroom. The lack of clarity and precision has re-

    sulted in a mixing of metaphors and the running together of two quite distinct

    matters-the nature of scientific knowledge and the nature of learning (Ogborn,

    1994). A s

    Ogborn points out, there is no necessary connection between the episte-

    mology of science and the methods by which it is learned, for it is like arguing

    that the way to learn poetry is by writing poetry, a relationship which at best may

    have only partial justification. This point has also been made by Hodson

    1988),

    Margetson

    1982),

    and others.

    However, Dana and Davis

    1993)

    maintain a different view, arguing that the tradi-

    tional objective view of knowledge leads to the belief that the process of teaching is

    one of telling and the process of learning one of memorization and recall. Now while

    this may be a true account of what has happened, and still happens in many societies,

    it is not a necessary or logical connection.

    As

    one author has pointed out:

    From the definition of objectivism as the search for truth, nothing follows about

    learning discovered truths as the m ere passive absorption of facts and their regurgita-

    tion. . It is quite possible to m aintain objectivism, . and reject the view that

    the teaching or learning of already discovered truths has to be conducted in such a

    crudely didactic manner. Nola, 199 5b, p. 4)

    Thus, the nature of science has no necessary bearing on the nature of teaching and

    learning science, for the former is a philosophical issue to do with the nature of sci-

    ence while the latter is an educational issue to do with the best way of educating non-

    scientists about science.

    Moreover, just as traditional, objective teachers have often failed to recognize the

    need to structure learning so that it is active, the advocates of constructivist methods

    of teaching have failed to recognize that there is a role for telling, showing and

    demonstrating. Teachers, we are told, should negotiate, facilitate, coconstruct,

    mediate, socialize, provide experiences, introduce, and make the cultural

    tools of science available, but never ever will they tell. Clearly what is needed here

    is the intellectual recognition that the commitment to a particular view of science

    says nothing about the manner in which it is taught. Just as it is fallacious to infer

    that objectivism implies didacticism, it is false to assume that a belief in construc-

    tivism implies that all knowledge must be negotiated. The rejection of the role of

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    16/30

    8 OSBORNE

    telling in pedagogy only confirms the suspicion that constructivists have difficulty

    with the notion of objective knowledge-and that what each student constructs

    needs only to make sense or be viable. That is, it is the act of constructing that is

    important and not the product of construction for constraints on what constitutes sci-

    entific knowledge are not recognized.

    Some evidence for the role and value of direct instruction can be found in the work

    of Muthukrishna et

    al. (1993). They point to the fact that, in a number of studies that

    address alternative frameworks directly, the success rate in changing childrens

    ideas, which ranges from 28 to

    69 ,

    s limited, and argue that their research, using

    an approach based on explicit instruction with a laser videodisc, which eliminated

    over 90 of common alternative frameworks shows that the common hypothesis

    that meaningful learning cannot result from explicit instruction may possibly be an

    overstatement. While their work can be criticized on the basis that the domain of

    earth sciences, in which this study took place, has little possibility of generating

    many strongly held intuitive ideas, it does show that not all science education re-

    quires a singular approach.

    In short, it would appear that there are significant problems for a paradigm which

    seeks to be a referent for pedagogic practice. By emphasizing its successes and con-

    veniently ignoring its weaknesses, constructivism has acquired the umbrella of an all-

    embracing theory, when it is at its best, a partial contribution to science education.

    This is not to argue that the process of education should be one

    of

    transmission, but

    simply that it must enable children to acquire and understand the powerful constructs

    and ideas of modem science and that any comprehensive theory of science education

    should address the issues of content, concepts, sequencing, cognitive demand, and

    the adjudication of competing theories.

    What constructivism does have to offer is a useful focus on the learner as an active

    participant in the learning process, a range of pedagogic practices which encourage

    the child to be active, and a body of empirical research findings which are invaluable

    for sensitizing teachers to the forms of scientific thought that children hold and their

    possible stages of development. The latter is particularly important, for if teachers are

    to change childrens understandings, it is important to be receptive to, and aware of,

    the manner and origins of childrens thought. Put simply, to teach a child about sci-

    ence, not only does it help to know something about science, it helps to know some-

    thing about the child. Research conducted from a constructivist paradigm in the past

    decade has made a major contribution to the latter.

    WHAT DO

    SCIENTISTS DO?

    The position taken here is that science education should attempt to communicate

    not only the practice of science, but also the beliefs that are widely held in the scien-

    tific community, and one of the basic tenets is that scientific knowledge is different

    Scientists establish their knowledge claims through a program of experimentation,

    verification, and peer review

    so

    that there exists a consensus which becomes their

    touchstone of reliability. Therefore, the position of constructivist authors does not

    represent the stance of most scientists whose views are more akin to that of Ziman

    who argues that:

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    17/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM

    69

    The objectivity of a well established science is thus comparable to that of a well-

    made map drawn

    by

    a great company of surveyors who have worked

    over

    the same

    ground

    along many different routes. (Ziman,1979,p. 108)

    And just as the child derives his or her well-founded confidence in the reality of

    everyday things from the sensorimotor bodily experience of childhood, by acting and

    intervening on the world,

    so

    does the scientist gain their confidence in the reality of

    scientific entities which are initially theoretical speculations.

    As

    cells are regularly

    manipulated under the microscope, or particles produced and detected in accelerators

    and bubble chambers, our belief in the reality of these entities and our knowledge of

    them grows.

    However, scientists thoughts and ideas

    are

    constrained by the way the world

    chooses to behave so that the methodological component of scientific epistemology

    is one in which maps are created to store and represent scientific information, Such

    maps are constructed by people who have worked over the same ground using many

    different routes. Scientists confidence in the objectivity of their descriptions is

    founded on the consensus of practice and ideas that emerges as the fruits of their

    work and actions on the world. It is this link which distinguishes science from other

    forms of knowledge. This is not to argue that science offers a moral exemplar to

    other disciplines, but simply to state that it provides knowledge of an objective and

    real world. Such knowledge is incomplete, curtailed, and limited but it grows through

    the creative efforts of individuals who continually strive to formulate new hypotheses

    about its nature and test these ideas experimentally. The ideas and theoretical entities

    they derive are initially human constructions, often the product of a contingent cul-

    tural event in history and extremely tentative. Through experimentation, knowledge

    of the adequacy and detail of these maps emerges, not always as in the case of

    wave-particle duality, but often, as in the case of the electron, the AIDS virus, etc.

    Just as the cartographers maps do not correspond with the terrain itself,

    so

    are the

    scientists maps separate and distinct from the real entities that they describe.

    However, in the same way that the former describe real features of the ground such

    as its elevation, land use, and vegetation,

    so

    do the maps of the scientist describe real

    features of the physical world. And just as the cartographer constructs new represen-

    tations that more closely approximate to the physical terrain,

    so

    does the scientists

    increasingly detailed descriptions give us a better knowledge of extant phenomena.

    REALISM

    REVISITED

    The practice of science, outlined above, concurs both with the predominant beliefs

    of individual scientists and an epistemology of modest realism. Furthermore, such a

    view does have pedagogic implications. The case for realism developed here is based

    on the arguments advanced by Harrk

    (1986)

    in

    Varieties of Realism.

    Harrk sensibly

    recognizes that maximal realism, the position of any individual who believes that

    theoretical statements are true or false by virtue of the way the world is, is far too

    strong and easily vulnerable to attack. Ptolemaic astronomy and continental drift are

    just two of many examples which demonstrate that there can be no place in science

    for a sure catalog of facts of the matter fixed by the way the world is (Hads

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    18/30

    70 OSBORNE

    emphasis). Instead, basing his approach on material practice, that is, what scientists

    do and say, he recognizes that neither the slogan reference determines sense, or

    sense determines reference, which contrast the role of ideas and sensation, will do

    as a basis for a theory of meaning. His important contribution is to recognize that:

    Sense determines the possibility of reference-that is, it directs a programm e of re-

    search- while reference, when achieved, brings about refinement of the sense.

    There is, over time, a dynamic, dialectic interaction between these two aspects

    of

    meaning.

    Harr6, 1986,p.

    33)

    This position shifts the locus of the argument about realism from the truth or falsity

    of statements to the question of the existence or nonexistence of the entities dis-

    cussed by science. Scientists are not asking Are statements of this theory true or

    false? and doing their best to answer but instead ask the question

    Do

    things, prop-

    erties, processes of this sort exist? and do their best within human limitations to find

    exemplars. This realist position is epistemically modest and does not make incorri-

    gible existential claims about reality. Rather it bases its knowledge claims on the

    fact that it is possible to secure reference to a referent, what

    Harr6

    terms referential

    realism.

    To

    establish the latter, Harr6 bases his argument on Gibsons theory of per-

    ception (Gibson,

    1979 ,

    which sees the object and the observer as part of an ambient

    array or energy flux, shaped by both the presence of the perceiver and the perceived.

    This array or flux provides information which is specific to the object, and it is the

    structures within the array caused by the object, what Ham6 terms the higher order

    invariants, that the organism perceives with its perceptual system. Such sensations

    are coarse-grained, but acceptance of a Gibsonian theory of perception explains how

    it is possible to perceive something generic-a thing, an event

    or

    a spatial relation.

    Only then does the cognitive operation enter into the process to interpret and define

    the information afforded by the object in the ambient array. If necessary, the organ-

    ism will use additional sensory organs to establish the nature of the higher order in-

    variants through an interactive process of exploration and feedback.

    The important point about the Gibsonian theory of perception is that it avoids the

    trap of making representations prior to sensations. For if categories and concepts are

    to be determined a priori-from what are they to be constructed? A Gibsonian ver-

    sion of perception shifts the point at which cognitive influences enter the act of per-

    ception to

    after

    rather than

    before

    a subtle but significant distinction which avoids

    the commitment to the transcendental necessity of categories a priori. Thus, a

    Gibsonian theory of perception is similarly modest. What is says is that things ex-

    ist e can perceive them and they are ontologically stable, but our description and

    beliefs about them can be revised.

    In arguing for a referential realism, Harr6 states that our interaction with, and sen-

    sory

    feedback from macroscopic objects allows us to know what the attributes of

    such entities are. Their ontological status is not in question but the notion that we ul-

    timately can know the truth about such objects is sensibly dismissed as a fruitless

    search. All that it attempts to show is that the objects of scientific investigation are

    relatively stable as opposed to the cluster of beliefs that we may hold about it.

    Consequently, what Lister observes as loose cells in an infected wound and Pasteur

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    19/30

    BEYOND

    CONSTRUCTIVISM

    71

    describes as external agents of infection exist and can be referred to through mate-

    rial practice. Referential relations and our descriptive vocabulary can be revised but

    the basic ontological sketch is not in question. For instance, the heart and the circula-

    tory system existed before Harvey first described them in 1628.

    Having established this carefully constructed epistemic position based on suc-

    cessful and unsuccessful acts of reference in which a real physical relation is estab-

    lished between the perceiver and an exemplary thing, HarrCs next significant step

    is to argue that there are three types of entities that we experience in the world

    which require not a singular theory of science but a triadic one. Realm 1 theories

    enable the classification and predictions about macroscopic objects which are tan-

    gible and accessible to sensorimotor experiences; thus, a typical realm 1 theory is

    classical kinematics-an area of common experience. The moon, the eye, a chair,

    a spring are all typical referents belonging to realm 1. Thus, for such objects,

    meaning in scientific cognition and discourse is typically provided by reference to

    samples which fix the meaning of descriptive terms, and hence is essentially ex-

    tralinguistic.

    Realm 2 theories are iconic in the sense that they represent unobservable entities

    which are only accessible to our senses through instrumentation such as bacteria and

    viruses. However, such entities and their behaviors are always observable, or poten-

    tially

    so, through the aid and assistance of technical artifacts. All such entities are the

    products of

    a representation

    of a physical system and its modes of behavior, which

    when first formulated, have not been observed. In realm 2 discourse, the objects of

    realm 1 serve as a basic ontology, but such discussion is much more dependent on in-

    tralinguistic meaning creation through the use of metaphor and simile.

    Harrk

    follows

    Soskice (1985) in arguing that:

    Metaphor is a trope through which new vocabulary is created. By means of it our

    conceptual grasp of a subject matter referent) is enhanced by the use of a term with

    a well-established context

    of

    use, and thus an existing deep gramm ar and set of

    asso-

    ciated comm onplaces. In this way, through metaphor, new vocabulary can be

    created within the existing structure

    of

    language,

    so

    securing the intelligibility

    .of

    the

    term in the context of use. Harri, 1986,p. 77)

    Hence, metaphor is not simply a useful adjunct for scientific thinking but an essential

    component of theory itself which leads to the discovery of hidden causes, or the pos-

    tulation of new theoretical entities. The vast majority of scientific theories are de-

    scriptions and hypotheses of realm 2 objects.

    Finally, realm

    3

    theories describe theoretical objects for which there is no direct

    evidence of their existence, such as quarks and black holes, whose descriptions are

    often mathematical. Such objects are beyond all possible experience but advances in

    technology may enable these objects to be observed and thus make an ontological

    shift into realm 2. For instance, prior to the invention of the electron microscope,

    viruses were unobservable and at the time would have typified the speculative realm

    3

    entity which the Higgs Boson currently does for particle physicists. Once again,

    our knowledge of these objects is dependent on the use of metaphor, but also the lan-

    guage of mathematics.

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    20/30

    72 OSBORNE

    Hacking (1983) also offers a realist interpretation of science that does make the

    important distinction between real and theoretical entities. Entities become real when

    they are manipulated by the experimenter who intervenes on the world. Using elec-

    trons as an example he argues that because we regularly set out to build, and often

    enough succeed in building new kinds of devices that use various well-understood

    causal properties of electrons such entities do exist. The essence of his argument is

    that the existence of electrons is not a hypothesis tested by the successful construc-

    tion of some artifact but the reverse-that the effective functioning of the newly

    built instrument is dependent on a modest number of home truths about electrons

    which are confirmed time and time again. For theories, Hacking advances a prag-

    matic modest realism following the arguments of Putnam (1975) that theories and

    their representations attempt to refer to some reality and science progresses because

    these theories improve and our descriptions are enhanced. Although we can never be

    certain that they are accurate representations, Hackings realist would argue that the

    phrase as certain as we can possibly be summarizes his or her views about the

    claims made about reality by theories.

    Hacking and Hm6 both present a clear argument for a realist epistemology based

    on an objective ontology. This position stands in contrast to those of philosophers

    like Rorty (1989) for whom there is nothing to be said about truth save that each of

    us will commend as

    true

    those beliefs which he or she finds good to believe. Rortys

    work i s a serious attempt to dethrone science from a pedestal where it offers a stan-

    dard of objectivity and rationality to which all other forms of enquiry must be com-

    pared. Thus the only way science can be seen as exemplary is that it offers a standard

    of practice for the provision of free and open encounter which provides suggestions

    about how the rest of culture might organize itself.

    As Matthews (1994) argues, modest realism is enough to go on with, and it is in-

    compatible with constructivism. Its limited theses are that there is an ontological re-

    ality; that scientific theories are human attempts to refer to this reality; that theories

    are confirmable by evidence (or falsifiable); and that there is a progression in scien-

    tific theories which produce increasingly accurate approximations and descriptions of

    that reality. Such a perspective does have limited pedagogic implications which are

    markedly different from those of constructivism.

    REALIST PEDAGOGY

    HarrCs interpretation of scientific theory accounts for two of the current problems

    within science education. First, since much of modem science is concerned with po-

    tential realm

    3

    entities, there is a natural inclination to forget the grounds on which

    such objects are formulated-our understanding of realm 1 and 2 objects. The spec-

    ulative nature of the discussion about black holes or the demise of the dinosaurs leads

    some to imagining that all science is simply a way of talking about the world with no

    substantive basis for its knowledge claims. The two most well-known attacks on sci-

    ence by the sociologists of science are both studies of scientists working in Cealm

    3-in one case on the development of our understanding of quarks (Pickering, 1984)

    and the other on the determination of the molecular structure of TRF hormone

    (Latour Woolgar; 1986). Consequently, the view arises that all science is an activ-

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    21/30

    BEYOND

    CONSTRUCTIVISM

    73

    ity requiring the construction of theoretical entities where the relation to any reality is

    at best tenuous or unjustifiable. But this is because the activity of research scientists

    working at the frontiers of our understanding with realm

    3

    entities has been portrayed

    as the activity of normative science.

    Second, in science education, we have attempted to ontologically shift some enti-

    ties, such as energy, from realm

    3

    to realm

    1

    with a failure to address the inevitable

    problems that arise out of attempting to make the intangible concrete and self-evi-

    dent. The debate about the teaching of energy that has occurred over the past decade

    is a good example of the pedagogic problems raised with, on the one hand, the argu-

    ment that the topic is too difficult and abstract for anybody younger than 18 (Warren,

    1983)

    and, on the other hand, the arguments of others (Carr Kirkwood,

    1988)

    that

    the topic should be included in the primary curriculum.

    More importantly, for the science educator, Harrks ideas provide a coherent ac-

    count of scientific epistemology which is more akin to that of practicing scientist and

    some tentative theoretical basis for the construction of a curriculum. Experiences of

    realm 1 macroscopic objects are those which the child uses to construct explanatory

    schemas of physical and biological phenomena, albeit fragmented and lacking any

    theoretical description other than an intuitive mechanics (Mariani Ogborn, 1991;

    Bliss et al.,

    1989;

    di Sessa,

    1988)

    and an intuitive biology (Carey,

    1985).

    If

    so,

    an

    early science education should attempt to build on and extend childrens experiences

    of macroscopic phenomena, introducing the child to the descriptive language of the

    scientist and the theoretical frameworks, the ideas of realm 2 and 3, which enable

    them to generalize from such experiences and to interpret their acts of perception

    with the scientists spectacles.

    Such an approach would encourage observational activities of a wide range of

    common macroscopic phenomena. For instance, the fact that all liquids can be made

    to disappear and reappear and that such properties are what scientists call evap-

    oration and condensation; that all animals have a mechanism for taking in oxygen

    and exhaling carbon dioxide; that springs and rubber bands stretch and that they all

    share a common pattern in the way in which they stretch. Thus, the sole purpose of

    such an education at this stage would be to enhance childrens discourse and to show

    that, with such a language, all phenomena are not uniquely contextualized but share

    universal properties. Moreover, such an approach would place a greater emphasis on

    introducing the theoretical description

    prior

    to observation and experience rather

    than a vain hope that the child might spontaneously discover the scientific explana-

    tion from an interpretation of their empirical data.

    From here, science education would move to examine the theoretical entities of

    science for which there is instrumental evidence-Harrks realm 2 entities.

    Typically, this would require an exploration of the particle model and the evidence to

    support it; the evidence of microscopy for the internal structure of plants; the evi-

    dence of dissection or models for the internal mechanisms of the body; the evidence

    for charged nature of matter; the nature of the Solar System, etc. All are entities

    whose ontological existence is inferred from the evidence of instrumentation.

    However, their existence can be related to realm 1 macroscopic objects, the entities

    of possible experience for children, through the use of direct reference and metaphor

    to construct models and representations.

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    22/30

    74

    OSBORNE

    Realm

    3

    entities are the abstractions of the human mind for which there is no in-

    strumental evidence. As such these entities are inferred to explain certain experimen-

    tal results-neutrinos and quarks are both classic examples. However, at a more

    mundane level, quantities such as speed, acceleration, current, charge, energy, the

    mole, and molecular biological mechanisms are such abstractions. These concepts

    can only be constructed on a sound scientific understanding of realm 1 and 2 entities.

    Hence, the idea of speed is constructed out of the pupils experiences of motion and

    the measurement of time and distance, both realm 1 entities and the idea of current

    constructed from observations of the brightness of bulbs and simple causal relation-

    ships. Cognitively such ideas are more demanding because they require the ability to

    envisage and manipulate imagined entities and their symbols for which there is no di-

    rect referent.

    In this way, HarrCs account of science provides a form and logic for the curricu-

    lum that bears a clear and transparent relationship to the structure and practice of sci-

    ence itself.

    n

    epistemology of modest realism insists that knowledge claims are

    checked against reality itself and thus avoids the relativist pitfall of the radical con-

    structivist who would ascribe validity to any viable theory that encapsulated per-

    sonal experience. More importantly,

    it

    would enable the curriculum developer to

    make decisions about content, a matter on which a constructivist epistemology says

    nothing. Yet, quite plainly, we choose not to teach children about special relativity,

    quantum mechanics, molecular biology, and the electronic configuration of chemical

    bonds because we know that such knowledge is not accessible to them until they

    have understood a wide body of other factual and theoretical information.

    Constructivism singularly fails to provide any reason why this should, or should not,

    be done.

    STYLES

    OF

    LEARNING

    Finally, there is one other issue that merits consideration which is the nature of the

    individual reaction to the style of learning offered by constructivist pedagogy. In re-

    acting against didacticism, constructivists in science education have chosen to place

    their emphasis on cooperative, discussion-based activities for the production

    of

    knowledge and ignore the fact that there may be a role for demonstrating, showing,

    or telling. For instance, Tobin (1990) argues for a learning model based on coopera-

    tive learning and social collaboration; the curriculum development work undertaken

    by Driver (1989) uses small groups of about four students which

    form

    the struc-

    tural unit around the scheme of activities; and Nussbaum and Novak (1981) advo-

    cate the use of brainstorming in the classroom as a pedagogic strategy. Others

    place an emphasis on interpretive discussion or listening discussion (Baird

    Northfield, 1992) and group activities such as games, role playing, and simulations

    (Bentley Watts, 1989). But the evidence of research would indicate that the ap-

    proach to learning offered by a constructivist pedagogy is preferred by some, but not

    all students, and likewise, is effective for some but not all.

    The literature on learning styles is extensive. Brophy and Good (1974) explored

    the effects of diverse cognitive styles and personality characteristics, while Good and

    Power

    (

    1976) examined the effect of affective characteristics (e.g., attitudes, interest,

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    23/30

    BEYOND CONSTRUCTIVISM

    75

    and motivation). However, some of the most interesting work has been undertaken by

    Pask (1976) and Entwistle (1981). Pask identified two main types of learning strategy

    used by different individuals: the serialist, who deployed a step-by-step strategy

    which examined one hypothesis and then the next in a simple linear progression; and,

    in contrast, the holist, who took a more global approach to problem solving, con-

    sidering multiple hypotheses simultaneously, and used a more individualistic ap-

    proach to learning. Pask found that both groups of students were capable of reaching

    the same level of understanding, but that their ways of attaining that understanding

    were

    very

    difSeerent. Holists prefer to start by forming an overall picture of what is be-

    ing learned while serialists attempt to integrate separate topics in a piecemeal form.

    Hence, while the holist is concerned with comprehension learning, constructing de-

    scriptions of what is known, the serialist takes an operational approach, attempting

    to master procedural details.

    One of the most important experiments conducted by Pask, which those who

    wholeheartedly advocate a constructivist pedagogy should note, was to match and

    mismatch sets

    of

    learning materials with students learning styles. The students in the

    matched conditions were able to answer most of the questions about what they had

    learned, whereas the mismatched students generally achieved below half marks.

    Entwistles work explored the personality factors that correlated with academic

    success in undergraduates. He identified three distinct personality types, whose ap-

    proaches to learning were all significantly different and who achieved success. The

    first group consisted of motivated students who were emotionally stable and were

    spurred by competition to demonstrations of intellectual mastery. The second group

    were the antithesis in that they were unrealistically pessimistic about their ability and

    haunted by the fear of failure. Driven by anxiety, these students had unconventional,

    though effective, approaches to studying. The final group were predominantly arts-

    based students and combined high verbal aptitude with good study methods and long

    hours of study.

    The important conclusion to be drawn from this kind of research is that students

    vary in their motivation and preferred learning styles, and that a teaching scheme

    based on a single perspective will only meet the needs of a subset of any group of

    children. Within science education itself, there are studies which support such an in-

    terpretation.

    For instance, in a study of 390 Spanish 15-year-olds learning styles, Kempa and

    Martin-Diaz (1990a, 1990b) identified four types of motivational patterns, driven out

    of a desire to either: (a) achieve; (b) satisfy their curiosity; (c) fulfill or discharge a

    duty; or (d) affiliate and interact with other people. These they call respectively the

    achievers, the curious, the conscientious, and the social. Using an 80-item

    Likert-type preference inventory, they then examined the relationships that existed

    between these motivational patterns and their liking for different instructional proce-

    dures. Only the social learners showed a strong preference for group activity and

    the opportunity to pursue ones own inquiry. In contrast, conscientious learners ac-

    tually exhibited a preference for didactic teaching and experimental work with in-

    structions. Curious learners preferred learning from books, discovery learning, and

    doing practical work. Achievers had no strong preferences for any mode of learn-

    ing. The clear point is that individuals vary in their preferred learning style and no

  • 8/10/2019 Sci. Ed. 1996 Osborne

    24/30

    7 OSBORNE

    one model will meet the diverse needs of different children. Further evidence that

    this is so can be found in the report of the PEEL Project where a pupil comments:

    Its about us learning about, and comprehending the work that teachers set.

    helping students learn better

    by

    revising the days work, and writing down in your

    diary what

    you

    have done. I didnt like doing it-I stopped about the second

    week we did it-it wasn t interesting . Baird North field, 1992 , p.

    57)

    That not all pupils find such an approach to their liking is important as this implies

    that there is no one strategy that will achieve success with all pupils. Kempa and

    Martin-Diaz argue that the only practicable solution to this problem is for teachers

    to use as wide a range [emphasis added] of instructional procedures as possible, in-

    stead of limiting themselves to one or two. Yet the danger in constructivist peda-

    gogy is an assumption that it offers an improved learning strategy for all pupils,

    whereas its major strength lies in offering an alternative-challenging teachers wed-

    ded to a didactic model of transmission by offering variety and diversity.

    Therefore, the evidence from research on learning styles would suggest that there

    is no single effective method for teaching and learning as students differ in their pref-

    erences. From a psychological perspective and a careful examination of the aims of

    teaching science, Claxton

    (1993)

    argues convincingly that a single-minded emphasis

    on conceptual development in science is inappropriate for all children. Instead, sci-

    ence education should be developing a wide repertoire of teaching methods that are

    custom-built for different aims and different cliente